Eugenics

Eugenics Redux: Reply to Unz and Alexis

On August 17, I published a rather lengthy essay titled “On the Need for Eugenics” in the Occidental Observer, stating my case for a relatively mild and benign form of eugenic policy.  This is necessary, I said, because of steady declines in the quality of the human genome that began around the year 1900.  Prior to this time, and for all 3 million years of human history, around 50% of all human infants and children died before they reached the age of reproduction—roughly 15 years old.  Certainly there were many causes for these deaths, but a key factor was the strength and health of the child; weaker or less-healthy children are more prone to illness, disease, violent death, and fatal injury, and this was nature’s way of removing humans with less-than-optimal genes from the gene pool, leaving the strongest and healthiest to reproduce.  While much of this differential mortality was unconnected to genetic factors, it is likely that children with larger burdens of harmful mutations were more likely to die early than those less burdened, helping to stabilize the overall human genome.

But thanks to the Industrial Revolution (which began circa 1700) and modernization in general, advances in medicine, hygiene, nutrition, science, and therapy allow nearly everyone born in the developed world to survive to reproductive age.  The “child mortality” (not infant mortality) rate of 50% fell to about 40% in 1900 among Western nations, and then dropped precipitously to 4% in 1950, and then to 0.4% today—a reduction by a factor of 100.  Today, 99.6% of all babies in the West survive to age 15, when they are biologically capable of reproducing.  Virtually everyone survives, regardless of their genetic well-being.

The problem is that, when everyone survives, we see an increase in the probability that harmful genetic variants are passed along to subsequent generations.  Due both to natural processes and to artificial sources, human genes undergo mutations at a fairly predictable rate.  Most of these mutations have no effect or only mildly negative ones, but about 2% are more substantially detrimental.  When nearly everyone survives, and a large enough fraction of people have children, these “deleterious mutations” accumulate in subsequent generations, leading to growing burdens of harmful genetic variants.  Without a purifying selection process, the number of negative mutations increases in each generation, such that after just three or four generations, concrete negative effects become apparent, potentially including declines in physical and mental health, fertility, and intelligence (the eminent geneticist Michael Lynch [2010, p. 966] estimates “serious” consequences for human fitness from mutation accumulation in modern human populations after “approximately six generations” of relaxed selection).  I presented some evidence that all of these things were happening, and that they were at least consistent with the effects of mutation accumulation.  If the process continues unabated into the future, before long, there will be serious repercussions affecting, directly or indirectly, nearly the entire human race.

Therefore, I said, we need to take action now to introduce an artificial selection that partially mimics the past natural selection: in essence, a eugenic policy in which the least healthy or most defective 50% of people are discouraged from reproducing.  Instead of dying, they can be disincentivized from having children, or, in the worst cases, sterilized; but not killed.  We can be much kinder than Mother Nature—who is a truly ruthless old dame when she wants to be.

This, in short, was my piece.  It was bolstered by some supportive claims from the ancient world and from a few modern-day geneticists whose work indicates that humanity faces a potentially very grave threat, including that we might descend into a “great planetary hospital,” a world in which “everyone would be an invalid.”  I must stress, however, that as far as I can tell, none of the scientists cited in my last piece or this current one supports eugenics; and indeed, many explicitly oppose it (e.g. Henneberg, You, Woodley, Sarraf, and Peñaherrera-Aguirre).

The Unz Critique

This original essay ran in TOO for a few days and was quickly picked up by Ron Unz for his aggregator site Unz.com.  My posting there drew hundreds of comments, including, unusually, many from Unz himself—all critical, some hyperbolically so.  Rhetorically speaking, he was emphatic: “I’m extremely skeptical about the analysis”; “filled with total rubbish”; anyone who would buy the genetic determinism argument “is simply an idiot”; and so on.  And on: his total comments are pushing 9,000 words, whereas my “very long” essay was only some 7,500 words.  Well, everyone is entitled to their opinion, I suppose, especially when you own the website.

But if Unz wants to convince readers of the foolishness of my piece, rhetoric won’t do it; he needs to make real counterarguments.  So, let’s see what those are.  I will review his substantive points in order of appearance, except for IQ issues which I defer to the end.  My replies follow each point:

  • “While dysgenics likely is a problem…it’s a relatively slow problem, probably operating over several generations.”

The question is, how many generations?  Lynch (2016: 873) says we can expect “notable changes in average preintervention phenotypes…on a timescale of a few generations, i.e., 100 years.”  This is the estimated onset of problems due to accumulated mutations; full effects, he suggests, won’t be felt for “two or three centuries.”  Notably, Unz never once mentions Lynch or his claims; apparently he is more comfortable refuting me than one of the most illustrious living geneticists.  (An important point: I am not inventing these claims.  Rather, I am drawing from experts in published academic journals, quoting them, and making plausible conclusions.)

I now have more information and more support for my views.  A team led by Maciej Henneberg published some relevant papers a few years ago.  Consider W. You and M. Henneberg, “Cancer incidence increasing globally” (2017). They studied rates of 27 kinds of cancer over 184 countries, determining that 12 cancers were likely due to environmental sources (viruses, toxins) and 15 were primarily genetic, i.e. correlated with relaxed natural selection and accumulated mutations.  At the outset, they note that “mutations are more common than previously thought,” and that “multiple mutations may accumulate in genomes over time spanning just a few generations.”  They continue:

When selection against a certain mutation does not operate, the frequency of mutated alleles doubles every generation.  The mutation load is directly proportional to the mutation rate, and inversely proportional to the rate of selection.  Thus, when selection rates approach zero, mutation load approaches infinity. … [There is] a real possibility of deterioration of biological integrity of human organisms, observable in the time of a few generations in most advanced societies. (pp. 140–141)

Again we see “in the time of a few generations,” that is, very short timeframes.  And if the frequency of mutated genes “doubles every generation” when selection is blocked, then indeed we have a nonlinear increase in mutated genes—more on this below.[1]  Nonlinear effects also may appear because “interactions between alleles of various loci may magnify mutation rates,” i.e., via positive feedback.

In any case, rates for all cancers, all ages, are shown to correlate strongly with relaxation of selection—see their Figure 1.  As mortality rates from birth to age 50 approaches zero, as they do today in most developed nations, the degree of correlation with cancer rate increases exponentially.  “The association between Is [degree of selection] and cancer incidence was strong and significant… [and] stronger in upper middle economic classification” (p. 151).  Correlation is not causation, of course, but there seems to be a real possibility that accumulated mutations have a noticeable and detrimental effect on human health—in a few generations.

Anyone who believes that genetic/dysgenic factors explain these gigantic changes in American health [obesity, diabetes] over merely the course of a couple of generations is simply an idiot.

I bring to your attention two studies: First, “Worldwide Increase of Obesity is Related to the Reduced Opportunity for Natural Selection” (Budnik and Henneberg, 2017).  The two authors correlated data for 159 countries with their index of relaxed selection.  They hypothesize that one can explain “the rise in obesity by recent changes in the operation of natural selection” (emphasis added).  “During the last century”—hence, since circa 1900—“the opportunity for natural selection through differential fertility and mortality has been decreasing very substantially, while it has been found that de novo mutations occur at greater rate than previously thought and the mutation load is substantial.”  Thus the time frame under discussion is just a few generations.

They found that “regression of obesity prevalence by country on Ibs values per country is an exponential function, with correlation coefficient 0.61.”  Therefore, the more modern, more ‘relaxed’ nations—the ones in which virtually every baby survives to childbearing age—have more obesity.  And given that obesity is strongly genetic (up to 70% heritability), this is consistent with a link between accumulated mutations and obesity—in just a few generations.  Evidently Budnik and Henneberg qualify as “idiots” for merely considering this possibility.

Second study: “Type 1 Diabetes Prevalence Increasing Globally and Regionally: The Role of Natural Selection and Life Expectancy at Birth” (You and Henneberg, 2016).  Similarly to the above, a study of 118 countries showed a strong and significant correlation between relaxed selection and Type 1 diabetes.  The piece opens thusly: “Type 1 diabetes (T1D) is an autoimmune disease with a strong genetic component.”  As to environmental causes for this disease, the authors are dismissive: “It has been postulated that environmental factors may be able to trigger an autoimmune [reaction], however, these environmental factors are [merely] circumstantial”.[2]

Their chief finding, though, is this: “Globally, TID [Type 1 diabetes] is noted to be exponentially [nonlinearly] related with Ibs” (r = 0.713, R2=0.53).  As the authors explain, “Overall, the operation of natural selection on contemporary populations is declining due to modern medicine [since circa 1850]. … Although T1D can be fatal, the majority of genetically-predisposed people do not develop T1D.  This allows for accumulation of genetic predisposition in human populations.  This accumulation will increase when fewer persons who developed a disease would die.”  Again, correlation is not causation, but this is the first sign that causal factors are at work.

And the time frame?  Reduced selection, they say, is a product of “modern medicine,” namely, insulin, which may have been “boosting T1D genes accumulation and prevalence of T1D.”  “Several generations have benefited from insulin since it was discovered and became available in the early 1920s [!].”  “Reduced natural selection boosted by insulin treatment of several generations may have enabled cumulative effect of TID genes frequency in human population to occur quickly and to be noticeable for a couple of decades.”  Therefore, their “several generations” really means, three or four generations, because insulin has only existed for 100 years.  And if it was noticeable “for a couple of decades,” i.e., since 2000, then the timeframe was only 80 years.

We have solidly-established biological mechanisms indicating that fructose consumption is directly related to the personal health problems under discussion.

There is a difference between Type-1 diabetes and Type-2; the former appears mostly in childhood and is more strongly genetic, while the latter occurs later in life and is a combination of genetic and environmental factors, including diet, which may indeed be the stronger effect.  Thus we cannot speak of “diabetes” generically, and neither Unz nor I made this distinction previously.

Regardless, I contend that mutation accumulation is doing considerable harm, alongside the confounding environmental factors, which may be helpful or harmful.  And the data supports this claim.

I’d guess that most of the changes in human characteristics discussed in this long article are 90–95% environmentally-determined.

In light of the above, call me skeptical.

Rethinking the IQ Question

The remainder of Unz’s substantive critical remarks center on the question of IQ.  In my original paper, I argued that, according to Lynch and others, negative genetic impacts on fitness due to accumulated mutations should begin to appear in “a few generations,” that is, around the 1980 to 1990 timeframe (given that the fall-off in child mortality began around 1900).  As I explained, the well-known Flynn Effect shows increasing IQ test scores from circa 1900 to about 1980, at roughly 3 IQ points per decade, when they began to level off.  We furthermore have evidence that, beginning around 1990, an “anti-Flynn” effect took hold, causing a decline in IQ scores of about 1 point per decade.  While again not constituting proof, the timing is suspiciously coincidental: just when we expect negative genetic effects to appear, IQ test scores flatten out and then decline.

But Unz will have none of this:

“I’m extremely skeptical that innate IQs could have possibly shifted by anything like 10 points in a century…”

The Flynn Effect “must be some sort of testing artifact.”

“We’re seeing better test-taking performance on IQ tests, probably due to better education, or more familiarity with tests, or greater intellectual stimulation, or something. Test scores have gone up but ‘real intelligence’ probably hasn’t.”

The Flynn Effect is “hardly consistent with [an alleged] huge decline in ‘real intelligence’ [since the 1920s].”

“The alleged evidence of declines in intelligence are only found in very obscure metrics such as color discernment.”

A few thoughts here:  First, very few serious psychometricians have ever claimed that “innate IQ” (or the g-factor; see below) actually increased in line with the Flynn Effect.  Second, there surely are some testing effects that have changed over time, including such mundane issues as an increased willingness to guess on multiple choice tests, which do seem to have increased scores.  Third, education is probably a key driver of the Flynn Effect, as are artificial score-improving developments like increasing test familiarity.  On the other hand, there are substantive correlates of the Effect indicating that facets of intelligence actually have increased. Fourth, there are in fact a number of indicators of a decline in intelligence, all unified by reference to an underlying or “innate” cognitive ability.

Unz attacks my numerical claims.  I cited sources claiming that newborns contain roughly 100 ‘de novo’ or new mutations, independent of, and in addition to, any “germline” mutations that they inherit from their parents (germline mutations occur in the sperm or eggs of the parents, and thus are passed on).  I also cited the fact that only about 2% of the de novo mutations are substantially deleterious.[3]  When I then gave a hypothetical example of 100 or 200 mutations in a newborn, Unz assumes I meant 100 or 200 deleterious mutations when in fact it would only be 2 or 4 (the 2% figure).  “Skrbina dropped a factor of fifty!” he cries.  But this is an irrelevant complaint.  If the total mutations are accumulating, so too are the 2% that are harmful (to the extent that selection is too weak to purge them).  If the total is increasing linearly or nonlinearly, so too are the 2%.  That said, my example was unclear and technically incorrect, and thus I retract that one paragraph.

Apart from this, Unz has a number of misconceptions about intelligence and IQ, and my initial essay did little to clarify the situation, so I will try again here—bearing in mind that I am neither a geneticist nor a psychometrician, but that I do have an advanced degree in mathematics and thus am generally able to analyze technical papers.

Intelligence is a complex characteristic, something that can be both integrated and differentiated.  Thus, researchers commonly speak of a ‘g-factor,’ where the ‘g’ stands for ‘general intelligence’; it is a fundamental cognitive ability that underlies many aspects of intelligence.  We can think of ‘g’ as the core of learning and problem-solving ability that most people intuitively equate with intelligence per se.

IQ, or intelligence quotient, is a test score summarizing performance on typically a large number of mental ability measures.  Indeed, it is a single score reflecting various abilities, which can include abstract reasoning, quantitative ability, verbal knowledge, memory capacity, and spatial manipulation skill.  There is a very strong correlation between IQ scores and general intelligence (‘g’) among individuals in a given population, such that people with higher IQ scores have higher general intelligence. But the story becomes more complicated when we consider variation in intelligence and IQ test scores of populations over time.

As is well known, intelligence (whether indexed as IQ score or ‘g’) is affected by both genetics and environment.  In adults, it now appears that about 80% of variation in IQ-test performance is attributable to genetic factors and the remaining 20% to variation in environment and measurement error.  But different aspects of intelligence are subject to different influences, and it is important to take them into account.

Perhaps the best available model for understanding variation in intelligence over time is the “co-occurrence model.”  This fits well with most of the data we have today and also can explain a number of paradoxes that have arisen (see Egeland 2022).  In the co-occurrence model, we can split intelligence along 2 axes:

1)  general (g) vs specialized (s).

2)  heritable/genetic (h) vs environmental (e)

Combining these two axes yields four components of intelligence:  general/heritable (g,h), general/enviro (g,e), specialized/heritable (s,h), and specialized/enviro (s,e).  It is theoretically possible for these components to vary independently of one another.

Furthermore, and apart from this, we can identify four factors affecting intelligence over the past 200 years:

1)  Environmental improvements (nutrition, medicine, therapy, educational techniques, etc.), since ca 1800.

2)  Declining child mortality and concurrent mutation accumulation, since ca 1900.

3)  Increasing environmental toxins and mutagens.[4]

The fourth factor was entirely neglected in my original piece, which is unfortunate, considering that it is perhaps the most significant.  Much genomic evidence is indicative of positive selection for intelligence in the recent human past (from at least 30,000 years ago up to the time of large-scale industrialization); that is, smarter people generally left more offspring.  Smarter people were better able to gather resources, to fend off threats, and to anticipate future events, leading to more access to mating partners and to more surviving children.

As industrialization began first in the UK, and then in parts of Europe and America, the pattern of selection for intelligence began to reverse, partly due to increasing availability of contraception which reduced the fertility advantage of smarter people, who were more likely to control their fertility than their less-intelligent counterparts.  Eventually, higher intelligence became associated with lower fertility.  This process accelerated through the twentieth century, especially after the 1960s, and is very significant today, as the most intelligent couples defer childbearing to obtain advanced degrees, to progress in their careers, or simply because they prefer one or two children to three, four, or more.  Today, the less intelligent have more surviving offspring than the more intelligent, and this has a negative effect on intelligence at the population level.[5]  Thus, we may identify a fourth factor:

4)  Selection against intelligence, since ca 1850.

Now, of the four factors, only (1), environmental improvements have been positive—but strongly so.  In particular, these improvements strongly influence the specialized/environmental component of intelligence. This likely explains the bulk of the Flynn Effect, even though there is solid evidence that other factors, such as increased guessing, test familiarity, and the like, artificially contribute to rising IQ test scores.

The other three factors—mutation accumulation, toxins and mutagens, and selection—have negative effects on intelligence, with selection apparently being the most potent of the three.  Notably, genetic factors dominate here, making the consequent loss of intelligence harder to undo.

For most of the twentieth century, factors contributing to the Flynn Effect swamped the dysgenic trends.  As a result, IQ scores showed a dramatic average rise of about three points per decade, across all countries that even partially benefitted from industrialization.  This occurred even as the negative factors began to suppress the general/heritable component of intelligence.[6]

Until the 1980s.  Around that time, it seems that factors allowing further boosts in the spcialized/environmental component became harder to sustain. The Flynn Effect has generally been slowing and even reversing in the developed world (“anti-Flynn Effect”), on a scale of about 1 point per decade or around 3 points per generation.  This decline may be due to worsening quality of education and intellectual stimulation; in any case, the causes are likely multi-faceted and in need of further research.  Furthermore, it is conceivable, but not yet demonstrated, that falling levels of general intelligence (‘g’) due to adverse genetic changes are weakening the ability of wealthy nations to sustain the beneficial environments that promoted the Flynn Effect in the first place.  This, at least, is the best account for the data that we have.

A strong piece of confirmation comes from a 2023 paper by Mingrui Wang, “Estimating the parental age effect on intelligence.”  Parental age is known to affect a child’s intelligence, and under the mutation accumulation thesis, the child’s IQ should decline as parents age and their sperm and eggs undergo periodic genetic mutation (sperm more so than eggs).[7]  The data, however, typically shows an inverted-U pattern, where the child’s IQ is low for teen parents, rises until parents are in their 30s, and then declines again.  Wang theorized that children do, in fact, undergo a steady decline in intelligence as parents age, but that the ‘environmental’ benefit of parents in their 30s—which is presumed to be stronger than for teens or old parents—masks this decline.

Wang thus controlled for the “polygenic score”—a genetic index of intelligence unfortunately accounting for only a small percentage of variance in the trait—to remove the confounding effects of parental intelligence and to isolate the effect of rising parent age.  After this adjustment, Wang showed that, indeed, child IQ steadily declines with parental age, for both father and mother.  (Message: have your children while young!)  Even at age 30, there are considerable mutations from both parents, and these accumulate over time.  Thus, if 30-year-old parents have kids who in turn become 30-year-old parents, and so on, we will see a steady, generational genetic decline in IQ.  Even at these modest ages, says Wang, “[the data] suggest a 7.5-point generational [IQ] decline in genetic variants underlying intelligence.”

Wang does offer one qualification, namely, that correcting for birth-order effects may reduce the estimated declines.  But they would remain substantial: “it would still suggest a 2.4-point generational [IQ] decline” deriving from genomic mutation.  However, it is unclear, says Wang, whether birth order should be corrected for, and if not, then it could be the case that intermediate results would obtain, i.e., something between 2.4 and 7.5 points per generation.  A bad outcome, in any case.

In sum: Between, say, 1850 and 1980, falling ‘g’ in the industrialized West occurred alongside environmental factors driving the Flynn Effect.  Since about 1990, however, while selection against intelligence and ongoing mutation accumulation are likely occurring, capacity to sustain the Flynn Effect has been weakening.  At a personal, individual level, this may not mean much; the generation of children today have an average IQ of around 97, compared to the prior generation’s mean of 100.  Individual families would not notice anything amiss, but teachers who deal with larger numbers of children will likely detect a downward shift.  But when today’s children grow to have children, that new generation will likely be in the range of 94 IQ—a noticeable decline from today’s adults.  On the scale of entire nations, or entire civilizations, this will certainly have an effect—in just a few generations.

The implications are serious.  Falling intelligence may well reduce the Western world’s ability to manage complex problems such as mutation accumulation itself, a process that could accelerate in the future.  The negative factors compound and interact, as Lynch noted:  “It is therefore plausible that the human mutation rate is destined to slowly increase toward exceptional levels,” leading to “to a sort of positive feedback loop” in which adverse effects appear rapidly and nonlinearly.

Genomic degradation affects more than intelligence, of course.  It will impact every aspect of fitness, including fertility and physical and mental health.  Adverse trends in, for example, fertility, obesity, cancer, diabetes, Parkinson’s, depression, suicide, while likely driven substantially by environmental factors, may, to a degree that is currently hard to quantify, reflect the falling genetic quality of human beings—hence all the issues I mentioned in my first essay.

A Look at the Big Picture

Finally, consider a few comments by the geneticist Alexey Kondrashov, as published in his book Crumbling Genome: The Impact of Deleterious Mutations on Humans (2017).  He notes at the start the figure of roughly 100 de novo mutations in newborns, remarking that, rather than just 2% of these being deleterious, that actually around 10% have negative effects: “Despite of the all elaborate mechanisms that a cell employs to handle its DNA with the utmost care, a newborn human carries about 100 new (de novo) mutations, originated in the germline of their parents, about 10% of which are substantially deleterious” (p. ix).

He continues:

Several percent of even young people suffer from overt diseases that are caused, exclusively or primarily, by pre‐existing and de novo mutations in their genomes. …  Milder, but still substantial, negative effects of mutations are harder to detect, but are even more pervasive.

Later in the book, he contemplates a future in which mutations accumulate over generations, leading to potentially tragic consequences.  Kondrashov is admittedly uncertain about the future (obviously), and he sketches out scenarios for the best case and the worst.  Best case: mutations are balanced by selective forces and therefore there is no accumulation moving forward.  Under this scenario, “deleterious alleles will never make their way into the top 10 problems facing humanity” (p. 231).

But this is more than offset by a negative possibility:

According to the pessimistic scenario, … [s]election against deleterious alleles is deeply relaxed under industrialized environments and cannot prevent accumulation of all but the most deleterious mutations. Thus, the mutational pressures on many traits will likely increase with time. As a result, frequencies of overt diseases, in particular those caused by impaired functioning of the brain, will increase rapidly, and the mean values of some key traits which characterize human wellness will decline by ~30–40% in the next 10 generations [thus, 3–4% per generation], making phenotypes that currently correspond to the bottom 10–20% of the population a new norm. Some characteristics of the population, such as the proportion of people with IQ above 140, will decline even more.

Soon, improvements of the environment will become unable to mask these declines. Thus, after only ~10 generations, societies will begin to crumble, and preventing this is as important as dealing with climate change and habitat loss.

And which outcome is more likely?  “The truth must be somewhere in between, and, I believe, is closer to the pessimistic scenario.”

Unz seems to believe that it is nonsensical to suggest that mutation accumulation could be contributing substantially to reductions in human health and fitness; but again, geneticists as eminent as Lynch and Kondrashov expect real harm from this phenomenon to appear on a relatively short timescale. It is unwise, given our current state of knowledge, to complacently assume that the effect of mutation accumulation on these trends is so minor as to be barely worthy of our consideration.

There are many other points I could make, of course.  Consider China:  Are they suffering the same effects as shown here, or are they not?  China followed a very different social and economic trajectory than Europe; their industrialization was comparatively much-delayed, and even as late as 1950, over 80% of Chinese were still farmers.  China’s modernization formally began only in the latter half of the twentieth century.  Thus, for instance, China did not experience a decline in child mortality circa 1900, but only much later.  Child mortality (to age 5) remained high through 1930, began a slow decline, then dropped off dramatically from 1950 onward—a full 50 years later than Europe.  Therefore, we should expect a corresponding period of time to elapse before evidence of increasing mutational load is as apparent in China as it is in the Western world.

Suffice it to say that Unz has a lot of work to do to establish that my piece was “total rubbish.”

Alexis Takes His Shot

Unz’s critique was followed a few days later by a truly impressive critical essay of some 27,000 words by a Black Catholic journalist and author, Jonas Alexis.  It appeared on 30 August on Unz.com.  Despite the massive length of this piece, my response will be briefer than the above.

It is clear that Alexis takes personal affront with my position, which is not surprising; as a Black and a Catholic, he has two intrinsic reasons to oppose eugenics.[8]  But to his credit, he generally avoids these as bases for his critique; in other words, he does not use theological arguments against me, and only tangentially does he employ  “White identity” assertions for his case.  Unfortunately for him, the arguments that he does use fail miserably.

He begins with a host of slanders and insults against me and against anyone aligned with me.  He speaks of my work as representing “mental gymnastics,” “selective citation,” “omission of evidence,” “deliberate misrepresentation,” “avoidance of scholarly responsibility,” “cherry-picking,” “intellectual solipsism”—we get the point.  Indeed, I am, he says, just another of many writers who “reveal themselves to be structurally hollow, methodologically flawed, historically irresponsible, and philosophically worthless.”  However, such rhetorical complaints won’t suffice.

Alexis then attempts a little ‘poisoning the well’ fallacy by declaring eugenics to be associated with “essentially Talmudic characteristics”; if the evil Jews are eugenic, then it must be a bad thing!  Or so he implies.  I’m with him on the Talmud, but there is nothing there that resembles the eugenic system I advocate.  The Talmud declares non-Jews to be less than human, to be virtual animals, and thus they can be maltreated, abused, exploited, and even killed if it serves Jewish interests.[9]  This, surely, explains the mindset of present-day Israelis who feel they can mass-murder Palestinians in Gaza with impunity.  As sympathetic as I am here, this has no bearing on my arguments.

This is followed by an attack on my scholarship.  Alexis cites a bare list of some 25 books on eugenics, lamenting that I have offered “no sustained engagement” with this body of work.  Indeed—nor did I cite any of the 200+ books on the subject published just since the year 2000.  That, of course, would have been entirely inappropriate for a short, popular essay on the topic, but I did offer a few thoughts along the line that virtually all such works are anti-eugenic.  Should a reader care to peruse those 200 books and let me know where I am wrong, I would welcome the effort.

More seriously, Alexis then refers to my citations of Plato, Seneca, and Plutarch in favor of a form of eugenics such as they had at that time—one which involved passive or active infanticide.  My point, of course, was that eugenics was seen as necessary in the ancient world, not that infanticide is a good idea.  But Alexis jumps on this issue, accusing me of endorsing similar policies in the present day.  To the contrary: I argued for a rather benign and sympathetic treatment for inferior or defective infants:

For infants and children to age 15, actions would be very limited. Their very immaturity would preclude much in the way of evaluation. Genetic testing is one obvious exception, and this could be performed on all children with the goal of identifying genetic predispositions for certain diseases or disabilities. Otherwise, the main priority with this group would be to give all the best possible environmental conditions for growth, learning, and healthy development. Upon reaching the age of 16, all would then undergo the standard evaluation process.

Nowhere do I suggest or imply infanticide.  It is simply unnecessary, given present-day knowledge and capabilities.

Worse, though, is when Alexis accuses me of somehow promoting “removal,” “elimination,” or “extermination” of the unfit.  This is ludicrous and utterly unsubstantiated by anything I wrote.  He seems to hold a kind of cartoon-image of eugenics, like evil Nazis slaughtering the subhumans, as depicted in any number of Hollywood propaganda films.  Once again, this is nowhere stated, suggested, or implied.  Under no conditions do I advocate killing or harming anyone.

Alexis next goes into a lengthy discussion of Kantian ethics in an attempt to prove that eugenics is incompatible with that view and therefore unethical.  As one who has taught ethics at the university-level for two decades, I know something of the subject matter.  Academically speaking, there are today three primary systems of ethics: virtue ethics (associated with Plato and Aristotle), utilitarianism (associated with Bentham and Mill), and deontological or duty-based ethics (associated with Kant).[10]  Each has their strengths and weaknesses, and none are trouble-free.

And yet somehow, Alexis latches on to Kantian ethics, thrusting it to the forefront as the definitive and only correct form of ethics.  Worse, he attempts to use Kant’s categorical imperative against me and against eugenics.  (The categorical imperative is a modern form of the Golden Rule: act only such that you can universalize your maxim or policy for action.  Or alternatively, treat others as ends and not merely as means.)  If you’re going to kill someone, says Alexis, you are not treating them as ends!  And, you can’t universalize killing!  Nice try, except (a) I never suggested or implied any killing, so this argument fails on its face; and (b) such ethics are guides for individual, personal action, and not intended as guides to social or group ethical actions.  My proposed eugenic policy is a social-level system intended to forestall the worst effects of genetic degradation and to promote the best human qualities.  Thus his argument fails on two grounds.

Furthermore, eugenics is eminently compatible with both utilitarian (“greatest good for the greatest number”) and virtue ethical approaches (witness Plato), if he wants to press that line of thinking.  There is clearly a strong ethical argument for saving humanity from genetic degradation and social collapse—unless, that is, you hold to a comical, Nazi-esque vision of mass murder.

Alexis then treats us to a sprawling discourse on a vast range of semi-related people and topics, including (but not limited to) Darwin, Malthus, Galton, British child labor in the 1800s, Karl Marx, the Bolshevik Revolution, White identity, “White trash,” Teddy Roosevelt, Madison Grant, anti-Catholicism…wow, and I thought this was a discussion about my little paper on eugenics.  It’s all interesting stuff, mostly history, but best saved for another day.

One issue of particular concern to Alexis is the problem of intelligent psychopaths, such as those running our government and our military.  If we select for intelligence, he asks, won’t we produce even more intelligent psychos?  And don’t such people pose a greater risk to society than any “unfit” ones?  Agreed, we don’t want such types running our society, but any eugenic scheme, even the most effective and far-sighted, cannot hope to stop all such people from coming to power.  I will elaborate below, but in my proposal, a panel of skilled elders assess youth upon reaching, say, age 16 and determine their overall fitness using a range of characteristics; intelligence is only one, and pathological tendencies would certainly be another.  Any budding “intelligent psychopath” would not be killed, but rather, discouraged from reproducing, and probably given help, as appropriate.  At the very least, he would not be passing along any psychopathic genes.

But this touches on a broader point:  Eugenics, even the best system, cannot solve every problem in society.  It cannot end sickness and disease, it cannot end crime, it cannot guarantee peace and happiness for all.  All it can do is to act to boost the quality of our collective gene pool by promoting our best qualities and minimizing our worst.  And this alone makes it worthwhile.

As a final matter here, I would note that, despite his extensive verbiage, Alexis offers precisely zero treatment of my central point: that industrial society has, through relaxed natural selection (low child mortality) and a variety of mutagens, set us on a course for a steady degradation of the human gene pool, leading to a calamitous future unless action is taken soon.  Alexis utterly ignores the science, the data, and the claims by the geneticists that I cited.  Apparently, he has no use for science at all.  This is his right, of course, but then we have no obligation to take him seriously.

Elaborating on an Action Plan

I closed my original essay with some brief thoughts on how a benign eugenics system might be structured.  It was just an outline, of course, and was only intended to point in one possible direction.  But this plan brought down more criticism from other readers, especially on Unz.com.  So let me respond to a few concerns.

I think we can identify three basic categories of eugenic policy:  (1) centralized policy established at the federal level, (2) personal action by individual people or couples, and (3) local, decentralized policy, but with federal support.  The first category rightly prompts concerns about a “self-appointed elite” (Alexis), or a bunch of Bill Gates or Kamala Harris or George Soros types, who determine which genetic qualities get promoted and, in the most extreme cases, who lives and who dies.  Such a notion rightly makes our skin crawl, and is certainly nothing that I would ever recommend.  No government bureaucracy, no federal politicians, can ever be trusted to make wise decisions along this line.

The second category is growing in popularity, and goes by various names, including ‘embryo selection’ and ‘designer babies.’  This can potentially take a few different forms.  Couples can extract several eggs from the woman, fertilize them with the man’s sperm, and then test the embryos for various genetic markers (intelligence, disease susceptibility, etc.), and then select the preferred one for implantation into the woman’s uterus.  Or as a variation, the woman can select donor sperm from high-quality men, preselected for one or more qualities, and fertilize and implant.  Or, in more advanced versions, couples could use a CRISPR-type technology to directly add, remove, or alter the genetic makeup of a developing embryo before implanting.  This is a high-tech solution to a technological problem, and if the past is any guide, it will almost certainly fail in the long run.  In any case, this is not what I recommend either.

My preferred approach is something like category (3): a very localized, very decentralized process by which local panels of elders who are skilled, knowledgeable, and aware of all the relevant matters of race, ethnicity, and genetics, are charged with assessing youth upon reaching age 16.  This is necessarily a local process.  Consider the numbers.  In the US today, there are about 4 million boys and girls aged 16, with the average state having 80,000 such individuals—all of whom would need to be assessed in a year, on my view.  This implies that some 6,600 would be evaluated per month, a process that would likely require around 100 panels, each assessing 60 to 70 youths per month, for the average state.  That’s a lot of evaluation; it is certainly far more than any handful of “self-appointed elite” could act on.[11]

I suppose our elite could try to legislate a certain outcome by prioritizing certain characteristics, like intelligence if they needed more scientists and engineers, or physical strength if their armed forces were found lagging.  But an essential aspect of the system would have to be a firm “hands-off” condition, keeping federal bureaucrats, politicians, and (more importantly) their donors far away from the specifics.  The government’s role would be to acknowledge the necessity of such a process, to support it in principle, perhaps to help fund it—and then stay out of the way.

Obviously, local panels, even within a given state, would have a wide variety of ranking metrics; subjective evaluations, such as beauty or physical attractiveness, would vary considerably.  So be it.  I believe that the situation will become severe enough that almost any process, almost any selection on almost any grounds, will be better than the alternative—doing nothing.  Even the sketchiest panel from the poorest, most backward rural area, could pick out those youths with higher intelligence, better looks, or superior health.  Yes, such a process could potentially get hijacked by corrupt locals for nepotistic or other self-serving purposes.  Even under the best circumstances, it is an imperfect process; but again, an imperfect process is better than nothing.

And this brings me to my final point.  For all my critics out there, my question to you is:  What is the alternative?  Doing nothing?  Given the accumulating evidence, this seems risky in the extreme.  Are we to just wait as ailments increase, abilities decline, society decays, and in the worst case, an entire civilization is put at risk?  How long?  And then what?  The longer we wait, the harder it will be to correct our path.

The only other option is an ultra-risky high-tech solution: genetic engineering of our fetuses.  Even our politically-correct scientists, who can barely stomach the consequences of their own research, are compelled to state that genetic engineering is our “only” option—because the alternative is a “morally reprehensible” system of eugenics.

Actually, there is a third alternative: accelerationism.  For the pessimists out there who feel that Western civilization is doomed anyway, then the best option is not only to let it collapse, but even to make it collapse sooner.  Bring on the mutations!  Bring on the disease!  Bring on the stupidity!  The sooner the better, they say, and then the end of civilization will be imminent.  Once that collapses, the small remnant of humanity will have to live, once again, as we have for millions of years: in small bands of hunter-gatherers.  And benevolent Nature will once again impose her strict, eugenic demands on child mortality—and then perhaps we will be on the road to a better future at last.

David Skrbina, PhD, is a retired professor of philosophy. For more on his work and writings, see www.davidskrbina.com


[1] I note here that selection rates are never going to be zero; there still is some degree of sexual selection, for example, and spontaneous abortions also act to purify some of the worst instances of genetic defect.

[2] They do, however, qualify this point: “Non-genetic (environmental) factors partially determine whether, and how, risk-associated genotypes may lead to overt T1D disease.”

[3] Kondrashov (2017, pp. ix, 141, 147) argues that the 2% figure is more like 10%—a substantial difference.  More on this below.

[4] Likely from the earliest days of the Industrial Revolution, ca 1700, when industrial processes, fossil fuel combustion, and new metals were first introduced into society on a large scale.  Mutagens increased through the 1800s and early 1900s, and accelerated after World War Two with the introduction of numerous synthetic chemicals, especially plastics.

[5] In cruder terms, we might call this the “Idiocracy Effect,” after the satirical 2006 film of the same name.

[6] The (g,e) component currently appears to be small to non-existent, and any specific trends in the (s,h) component are currently unknown.

[7] These count as both germline and de novo mutations, since they are spontaneous and heritable.

[8] As a Christian, he takes particular offence at my popular book, The Jesus Hoax.  But that is another topic altogether.

[9] The Talmud is a massive compendium on Jewish rules for living and interacting with Gentiles, drawn roughly from interpretations of the Old Testament.  It was condensed down to a practical guide called the Shulchan Aruch in 1565.  For a good critical assessment of this work, see Erich Bischoff, The Book of the Shulchan Aruch (2023).

[10] Outside of formal philosophy, we also have various systems of religious or theological ethics, but I set those aside here.

[11] Realistically, anything like this proposal is probably impossible in a large nation like the US.  In reality, it would likely require state secession and the restoration of small-scale government to implement any policy as far-reaching as this.

On the Need for Eugenics

Eugenics is one of those ideas that has come to acquire a negative reputation for all the wrong reasons. Under pressure from mainstream academics and writers since World War Two, and largely due to its association with National Socialism, the very concept of eugenics has been derided and defamed for decades. Today it is widely seen as misguided, racist, or as some downright evil social-programming scheme; but in fact, as I will argue, it is vital for our collective survival.

Unsurprisingly, basic definitions are highly biased. The Cambridge Dictionary calls it:

the idea that it is possible to improve humans by allowing only particular people to produce children, which most people now do not accept or support because of the idea’s connection with racist and Nazi theories and actions.

Wikipedia tendentiously defines it as “a set of largely discredited beliefs and practices that aim to improve the genetic quality of a human population.” The slanted tone continues: “Historically, eugenicists have attempted to alter the frequency of various human phenotypes by inhibiting the fertility of those considered inferior, or promoting that of those considered superior.” It sounds bad, wrong, malevolent…especially for those on the wrong end of the ‘superiority’ spectrum. But in fact, it is normal, natural, and necessary for human beings, especially in the modern technological era. The primary questions now are not whether or not we need it, but rather what form, and of what intensity, a eugenic program should be implemented.

But let me start with some fairly straightforward observations. I claim that everyone, already, is a eugenicist—they just don’t use the term. The word ‘eugenic’ comes from the Greek eu (good) + genos (birth), related to genea (race) and genesis (origin). Eugenic has the sense of ‘good birth,’ ‘good stock,’ or in more scientific terms, ‘good genes.’ For themselves, everyone naturally wants to be of good stock, to have good genes; good genes typically imply good looks, health, intelligence, strength, longevity, and a robust personality. We cannot affect our genes, but still, we somehow hope that we have good ones and that any personal problems or health issues will somehow be ultimately controlled or remedied by our ‘good stock.’

It is a similar case, I think, for any potential partners or spouses that we might seek out. I think it is safe to say that, when young, most of us want mates who are beautiful or handsome (however defined), strong (in men) or feminine (in women), intelligent (at least, comparable to ourselves), and healthy. This is not to say that other non-genetic factors do not matter: women may seek wealthy men, for example, who can serve as good providers. Men may seek a ‘trophy wife’ simply because she is desired by other men. And there are other pragmatic concerns: In real life, we typically cannot find a willing partner with all these desirable qualities, and so we all eventually make compromises; but still, the vast majority of us seek mates with good genes.

There are, of course, sound biological reasons for this. For most people, a mate is someone to have children with, and we all, surely, want children with good genes: beautiful, smart, strong, healthy. Such children are a blessing in their own right and they are a blessing to society and humanity. Children of good stock grow up and live long enough to have healthy children of their own, thus sustaining and strengthening the community. Conversely, sickly, weak, or malformed children are a terrible burden, both to their parents and to society—though few will admit it. Parents of defective children prattle on about how their child is a ‘miracle’ or a ‘gift,’ but this is simply making the best of a bad situation. No one wishes for defective children, either for themselves or for others. We all want children with good genes, and we take action to try to ensure this. We all are eugenicists.

A Bit of History

This is hardly new news; it has been understood for thousands of years that humans, like all creatures, need to attend to ‘good breeding’ if they want to thrive. The earliest detailed account comes from Plato’s Republic, circa 375 BC, where he analyzes the need to have the best possible leaders for the polis (city-state). “Is there anything better for a polis than having the best possible men and women as its citizens? There isn’t.”[1]

Marriage is an important and valuable institution, says Plato, and therefore it should be made as sacred as possible. A sacred marriage is beneficial to the society, and beneficial partnerships result from mating the best men with the best women. “The best men must have sex with the best women as often as possible” (459d), whereas the most inferior men and women should rarely have sex. Children resulting from the best matches will be fully supported by the state, whereas the others will be neglected and perhaps left to die: “the former’s offspring must be reared but not the latter.” For the elite, says Plato, this can be done by removing infants from their parents and having the state raise them—no member of the elite should know his own children; this way, he will fight for them all.

Sexual unions based on individual choice are precarious and arbitrary; therefore, Plato concludes, we need to make special arrangements to encourage the best mating with the best, and having as many children as possible:

Certain festivals and sacrifices will be established by law, at which we’ll bring the [prospective] brides and grooms together, and we’ll direct our poets to compose appropriate hymns for the marriages that take place. … Then there’ll have to be some sophisticated lotteries introduced, so that at each marriage, the inferior people we mentioned will blame luck rather than the rulers when they aren’t chosen.

In this scheme, the rulers hold a high responsibility to assess the youth and to ‘rig the game’ in favor of the best. Here, the end justifies the means.

And among other prizes and rewards, the young men who are good in war or other things must be given permission to have sex with the women more often, since this will also be a good pretext for having them father as many of the children as possible. (460b)

If the rulers are wise and their intentions are good, the polis will flourish. Granted, in the Republic, Plato’s system is extreme: the best women become primarily baby-making machines, turning out the best future guardians while in their reproductive prime (20 to 40 years of age, he says), with the state providing all possible assistance and support. Any future system need not be so intense, of course; elements of Plato’s scheme could be adopted as conditions allow.

It is widely believed that Plato drew many aspects of his ideal city-state from the real-life Sparta, which seems to have actually implemented a kind of eugenic system. Writing a few centuries later, Plutarch made this interesting recollection:

[A Spartan] offspring was not reared at the will of the father, but was taken and carried by him to a place called Lesche,⁠ where the elders of the tribes officially examined the infant, and if it was well-built and sturdy, they ordered the father to rear it, and assigned it one of the 9,000 lots of land. But if it was ill-born and deformed, they sent it to the so‑called Apothetae, a chasm-like place at the foot of Mount Taÿgetus, in the conviction that the life of that which nature had not well equipped at the very beginning for health and strength, was of no advantage either to itself or the state.

On the same principle, the women used to bathe their new-born babes not with water, but with wine, thus making a sort of test of their constitutions. For it is said that epileptic and sickly infants are thrown into convulsions by the strong wine and lose their senses, while the healthy ones are rather tempered by it, like steel, and given a firm habit of body.[2]

The Romans, too, seem to have practiced a form of eugenics. In his treatise On Anger, circa 45 AD, Seneca writes:

We put down mad dogs; we kill the wild, untamed ox; we use the knife on sick sheep to stop their inflecting the flock; we destroy abnormal offspring at birth; children, too, if they are born weak or deformed, we drown. Yet this is not the work of anger, but of reason—to separate the sound from the worthless. (I.15.2)

Not anger, not cruelty, not maliciousness—but reason. If there is one lesson from these ancient sources, it is this: A wise society will not allow all children to grow to adulthood. The danger is too great. Eugenics is rational, and even in the pre-industrial age, it was seen as necessary. How much more so today, with the vast dysgenic pressures of modern life?

Nature is Eugenic, Technology is Dysgenic

Throughout the course of evolution, and for all lifeforms, nature has conducted a relentless sifting and selection process by which “the fittest” survive and flourish—where fitness is determined by the environmental conditions at hand and, ultimately, by the number of viable offspring left behind. In general, and to obviously simplify the story, stronger, faster, and more ‘clever’ organisms survive better than others of lesser qualities, reproduce more, and produce the healthiest and fittest offspring. By this process, Nature took around 2 billion years to produce higher lifeforms—those with a complex cellular structure—and another 2 billion to attain the so-called Cambrian explosion of complex life. Primates have been around for nearly 100 million years, and humans for about 3 million. Over this whole time, eugenic Nature sifted out the weak, sickly, and malformed, and allowed the strong and healthy to flourish, driving biological life onward and upward.

In all ancient human societies—which were small hunter-gatherer societies, until just a few thousand years ago—nature was ruthlessly eugenic. In rough terms, in ancient societies, about one quarter of all infants died before age one, and about half died before puberty, that is, before they could reproduce.[3] Therefore, simply to maintain a stable population, hunter-gatherer women had to have, on average, at least four children, so that at least two would survive to adulthood. Less than four meant inevitable social decline; more than four led to growth and relative social wellbeing.

But most importantly, the weakest 50% of humanity never lived to reproduce. Only the best half, the fittest, procreated. Over time, this allowed humanity to progress from Australopithecus to Homo Erectus to Homo Sapiens. It allowed the appearance of an Akhenaten, a Homer, a Socrates, a Plato, and an Aristotle. Individually, of course, it was tragic; mothers routinely lost half their infants or children. But collectively, it was a godsend. It removed the weakest and the sickliest from the gene pool, allowing the species to flourish. It eliminated many of the imbeciles and dysfunctionals, and allowed the appearance of geniuses.

But things began to change with the Industrial Revolution, circa 1700. New energy sources, advances in medicine, and increased food production initiated a long-term process that resulted in a reduction of childhood death rates. Rates that had stubbornly held at 50% for millennia declined to around 40% for most Western nations by 1900—and then they plummeted: to around 4% by 1950, and then to about 0.4% today.[4] It is an astonishing story: a modern technological miracle.

This, of course, has been uniformly hailed as good news. Mothers everywhere no longer have to worry about the loss of half of their young children. Today, 99.6% of all babies in the industrial West live beyond age 15, and can look forward soon thereafter to children of their own. Volk and Atkinson (2013, p. 183) call it “one of the greatest of all human achievements…the 50-fold modern increase in child survival.” This, surely, is an unconditional good; what could be better than that?

Actually, while good news for individual mothers and families, it is an unmitigated disaster for the human race. In fact, a double-disaster: on the one hand, it allowed the global population to explode, from 1.6 billion in 1900 to 8.2 billion today. This growth in human numbers, accompanied by a growth in per capita consumption, is rapidly depleting the planetary ecosystem, diminishing or eliminating other species, and exhausting the Earth’s capacity to support higher lifeforms. On this count alone, we might well drive ourselves to extinction.[5]

But on the other hand, we also have the rapidly accumulating dysgenic effects of near-universal survival. When nature killed off half of all children, she was doing us a huge favor by removing disadvantageous genes (“deleterious mutations,” in the literature) from the human gene pool. Now, with virtually all children surviving to reproductive age, all genes, good and bad, reproduce. This will inevitably have disastrous consequences in the long run.

The point cannot be over-emphasized: For some 3 million years, half of all human children died before they could reproduce. It seems to have been a constant of human existence, something like a law of nature. But then, literally 100 years ago, in the lifespan of a single human being, the child death rate dropped to virtually zero. Now, virtually all children (99.6%, in the industrial West) survive to their child-bearing years, and most of them will have at least one child.[6] This fact cannot but have monumental effects on the human race.

The details of genetic mutation are, naturally, highly technical, but we can summarize the central mechanisms and effects. We can identify three categories of genetic mutation: somatic (bodily), germline, and de novo. Somatic mutations may occur in any reproducing cell throughout a person’s lifetime, and can result in a variety of diseases, including cancers and psychological disorders. Importantly, though, these are not heritable; they cannot be passed along to the next generation. Germline mutations, by contrast, occur in sperm and egg cells, and thus are passed along. Thirdly, de novo (‘new’) mutations occur spontaneously upon conception or in a newly-formed embryo; these are not inherited from either parent, but they are passed along eventually to that child’s children. Every newborn, it is estimated, has about 100 de novo genetic mutations, most of which are neutral in terms of health or fitness, but some (about 2%) are mildly negative, and in a few cases, are fatal.

Fatal mutations are not the problem: far worse are deleterious but non-fatal mutations that allow the holder to live to reproductive age, to have children, and to pass the defects along to the next generation—which of course adds its own de novo mutations. Over time, the mutational load increases and genetic fitness declines.

Worse, as the mutations tend to accumulate, they grow exponentially. Again, to over-simplify, if a given child has 100 de novo mutations and it grows up and mates with another person with 100 mutations, the resultant offspring will inherit 200 mutations—and then add another 100 de novo of its own, yielding 300 total. If that person mates with someone who also holds 300 mutations, the offspring will have 600, plus 100 new, and thus 700 total. The next generation would have 1500; and so on. This is an accelerating increase, and within only a few generations, the mutational load would yield significant effects.

It has been known for decades that an accumulation of deleterious mutations could, over time, be harmful to humanity. It has also been known that modern technological innovations (medicine, health care) have relaxed the usual selection criteria that operated for millennia, by allowing children with significant, though perhaps hidden, genetic defects to live to reproductive age. In 1950, the geneticist Hermann Muller published a paper, “Our load of mutations,” arguing that “advances in general technology” and the many “techniques of civilization” were relaxing selection pressure, thus causing humans in the industrialized world to accumulate defects that would normally be eliminated. Modern Americans, he said, suffer from “inborn disabilities” amounting to “at least a 20% natural disadvantage” in fitness, versus our primitive ancestors. If this trend continues, it will worsen to the point where we become almost completely disabled:

[I]nstead of people’s time and energy being mainly spent in the struggle with external enemies of a primitive kind such as famine, climatic difficulties, and wild beasts, they would be devoted chiefly to the effort to live carefully, to spare and to prop up their own feeblenesses, to soothe their inner disharmonies and, in general, to doctor themselves as effectively as possible. For everyone would be an invalid, with his own special familial twists.

“Everyone would be an invalid”—this is our future, if we take no action. And not our distant future; it is happening now.

Two Important Articles

More recent and more important writing on this topic comes from biologist Michael Lynch. In his strikingly blunt 2010 article “Rate, Molecular Spectrum, and Consequences of Human Mutation,” he notes at the outset that “the long-term consequences…of deleterious-mutation accumulation” will likely lead to “a substantial reduction in human fitness…over the next few centuries in industrialized societies”—unless “novel means of genetic intervention” are employed.

After several pages of technical analysis, Lynch offers a look at those long-term consequences:

Because most complex traits in humans have very high heritabilities [that is, are strongly genetically-determined], the concern then is that unique aspects of human culture, religion, and other social interactions with well-intentioned short-term benefits will eventually lead to the long-term genetic deterioration of the human gene pool. … [I]t is hard to escape the conclusion that we are progressively moving in this direction. (p. 966)

The build-up of genetic mutations must periodically be cleansed from the population if they are not to cause long-term damage, and this is precisely what nature does so effectively:

The fundamental requirement for the maintenance of a species’ genetic integrity and long-term viability is that the loss of mean fitness by the recurrent input of deleterious mutations each generation must be balanced by the removal of such mutations by natural selection. If the effectiveness of the latter is eliminated, normal viability and fertility can be maintained to a certain extent by modifying the environment to ameliorate the immediate effects of mutations, but this is ultimately an unsustainable situation, as buffering the effects of degenerative mutations would require a matching cumulative level of investment in pharmaceuticals, behavioral therapies, and other forms of medical intervention.

Given the relatively high human mutation rate and the fact that a relaxation of natural selection typically leads to 0.1% to 1.5% decline in fitness per generation in other animal species with lower mutation rates, this type of scenario has now gained a level of quantitative credence that was absent when Muller [see above] first raised the issue. (italics added)

Nature continually prunes away bad genes, but since, for the past century, this no longer happens, we can buy some time with a combination of drugs, therapy, etc. But this is not, and cannot be, a long-term solution, says Lynch; the mutations will keep accumulating, creating ever-greater problems. Eventually, our best remedies will fail.

Since our childhood death rate is now functionally zero, we in the West have effectively eliminated (“completely relaxed”) the natural selection process; as a result, “the expected decline in fitness associated with mutations in coding DNA alone appears to be on the order of 1% to 3% per generation.”

But this is the optimistic scenario. To this we must add “contributions from other forms of mutations” (outside of DNA coding regions). And then there is the effect of an increase in mutation rate due to environmental mutagens (chemicals, radiation, etc.), which could cause a doubling in the rate. In sum, we are looking at potentially a 10% decline in fitness per generation, and up to 60% over two centuries. Lynch closes with this:

The preceding observations paint a rather stark picture. At least in highly industrialized societies, the impact of deleterious mutations is accumulating on a time scale that is approximately the same as that for scenarios associated with global warming. … Without a reduction in the germline transmission of deleterious mutations, the mean phenotypes of the residents of industrialized nations are likely to be rather different in just two or three centuries, with significant incapacitation at the morphological, physiological, and neurobiological levels.

…recalling Muller’s prediction that “everyone would be an invalid.”

Six years later, Lynch wrote a less technical “perspectives” essay for the journal Genetics in which he elaborated on these themes.[7] After repeating the fact that “an average newborn contains ~100 de novo mutations,” he reflects on the all-important “deleterious germline mutations” that accumulate over time and over generations. Lynch acknowledges that although our medical industry has been brilliant at inventing new treatments, “the myriad of clinical procedures for mitigating the consequences of bad genes (e.g., surgical procedures, pharmaceuticals, nutritional supplements, and physical and psychiatric therapies) can only result in the [further] relaxation of natural selection against a broad class of deleterious mutations.” This is a hugely important point: the better that our medical treatments become, the worse the situation in the long run, because such treatments only allow more individuals to live, to reproduce, and to pass along bad genes. Putting it bluntly: Medical treatment provides short-term benefits with long-term costs; the better our treatments, the worse the long-term effects.

Worse, the mutations may cause the mutation rate itself to increase. The relaxation of selection pressure, thanks to modern technological life, likely will affect both somatic and germline mutation rates. “It is therefore plausible that the human mutation rate is destined to slowly increase toward exceptional levels.” This could lead, says Lynch, “to a sort of positive feedback loop” that would cause accelerating problems.

To recap the situation: After millions of years of evolution, Nature has figured out how to remove deleterious mutations roughly as fast as they are introduced. Now, though, Nature is removing none of them, even as the rate of mutation may be speeding up—a compound crisis. If humanity is to avoid a catastrophic future, artificial selection will be needed to remove deleterious mutations from the gene pool.

Lynch closes with some interesting comments in his “long-term prognosis”:

From the standpoint of individual survivorship, there is little question that natural selection has been substantially relaxed for the past century or so. …

The preceding arguments need not imply that human behavior by natural selection has come to a standstill, one key issue being that natural selection is a function of both survival and reproduction. Even if variance in survival were to be eliminated entirely, phenotypes that are associated with [higher] reproductive output will inevitably be promoted by the blind forces of selection.

However, another aspect of modern human behavior—the tendency toward families of similar size (the two-child syndrome in middle-class neighborhoods in westernized societies)—may thwart this aspect of selection as well. Notably, this very strategy (equilibration of family sizes) has been used to accumulate deleterious mutations in experimental populations of Drosophila [fruit flies], yielding a 0.2–2% decline in fitness per generation.

In other words, the mere fact that a two-child or three-child family is something of a norm in Western society today, by itself, seems to lead to a decline in genetic fitness. Nature seems to ‘want’ a variety of family sizes, small to large, which effectively offsets the natural accumulation of mutations. Lynch continues:

Sexual selection [i.e. individual choice of mate] presumably continues to play some role in human evolution, although cosmetic surgery, acquisition of wealth, and other factors may relax this as well. … Clearly, the issues here are highly complicated, and it is by no means even certain that traits that are beneficial in an absolute sense (e.g., exceptional physical or mental attributes) are the ones currently being promoted by natural or sexual selection.

Thus, without any compelling counterarguments at this time, it remains difficult to escape the conclusion that numerous physical and psychological attributes are likely to slowly deteriorate in technologically advanced societies, with notable changes in average preintervention phenotypes expected on a timescale of a few generations, i.e., 100 years, in societies where medical care is widely applied. In the United States, the incidences of a variety of afflictions including autism, male infertility, asthma, immune-system disorders, diabetes, etc., already exhibit increases exceeding the expected rate. Much of this change is almost certainly due to alterations in environmental factors. However, mitigating these effects by modifications in behavior and/or medical intervention will also simply exacerbate the issues noted above by relaxing selection on any underlying genetic factors. (p. 873)

“What will it take,” asks Lynch, “to promote serious discourse on the slowly emerging, long-term negative consequences” of genetic mutation? Doing nothing, he says, could lead to “a slow walk down the path to what Hamilton (2001) called ‘the great Planetary Hospital.’”[8]

For all this, it appears that only a handful of research articles, dating back to the mid-1990s, directly tackle this issue.[9] And to my knowledge, only one book seriously addresses it: Modernity and Cultural Decline (2019).[10] The authors bravely tackle, straight-on, the genetic degradation caused by technological society, adding the effects of so-called epigenetic changes which involve heritable changes outside of alterations in DNA. Epigenetics could be yet another accelerating factor.

The Evidence

So a relevant question: Is there any evidence today of genetic decline? Lynch (2016) suggested that there is, and the data are even stronger today. Decline in fitness is generally measured in terms of declining fertility and declining adaptability, such as via declines in health. Consider first fertility: it is well-known that Western nations have long experienced declining fertility, measured as number of children born to the average woman in her lifetime. In the U.S., the fertility rate was around 3.25 in 1900, dropped to about 2.25 during World War Two, jumped up to 3.6 by the mid-1950s, and then began a rapid decline to 1.74 in 1976 and around 1.6 today (anything below 2.1 will lead, in the long run, to population decline). Europe followed a similar trajectory, plummeting from a rate of 2.7 in 1950, to 1.4 in 1998, recovering a bit, and then dropping again to around 1.38.

There are, of course, many factors to this situation, and even for the experts, “the general reasons for the extended decline are not well understood.” But we clearly cannot rule out genetic factors, and specifically declines in genetic fitness. The research is mixed. On the one hand, a recent study argues that, based on mutations in mice and a correspondingly small decline in fertility, that, “when extrapolated to humans,” any small rate of fitness loss “should not be of concern in the foreseeable future”—at least in terms of fertility. On the other hand, Aitken (2024) argues that smaller family sizes (as found in technologically advanced societies) and the growing use of hi-tech artificial insemination procedures will “decrease selection pressure on high fertility genes, leading to a progressive loss of human fecundity.” The inevitable result of this reduced selection pressure “will be the progressive accumulation of poor fertility genotypes.” Worse, such factors create “several congenital, pathological conditions” unrelated to fertility. The social implications of all this, he adds, “are potentially devastating.”

Beyond the issue of fertility, we have evidence of a general decline in human health and wellbeing, at least in the industrial nations. There are a variety of warning signs: Parkinson’s disease, for example, was diagnosed in 0.12% of the US population in 1970, and today it is around 0.3%—nearly triple the rate. Alzheimer’s disease likewise increased from a rate of 1.3% in 1980 to about 2.1% of American adults today. Some forms of cancer are on a downward trend but others are rising, including breast, prostate, uterine, pancreatic, kidney, and skin cancer. In men, since 1975, prostate cancer is up around 15%; liver cancer, around 50%; and melanoma, around 100%. In women over the same period, breast cancer is up about 30%; melanoma, 50%; and lung cancer, around 60%. Especially revealing are rates in young people: those in their 40s are seeing rising rates of endocrine cancer; in their 30s, rising liver and ovary cancer, and lymphoma; and in their 20s, thyroid and soft tissue cancers are up.

The surge in childhood obesity is well known. In 1963, about 5% of American youth were obese, and today it is around 20%. This is related to a rise in diabetes: in 1958, the overall US rate was only 0.93%; in 2014, it was 9.3%; and today, around 15.7% of all Americans have some form of diabetes.

And then we are dealing with myriad psychological disorders. The explosion in childhood autism, for example, gets a lot of attention but hard figures are difficult to come by, owing to the constantly evolving classification scheme used by doctors. But some things are more concrete: Prescriptions for autism- and ADHD-related drugs increased by 70% since 2011. Suicides in the US are up by 36% since 2000. And depression is dramatically higher in recent years: The number of those diagnosed with depression at least once in their lives rose from 19% in 2015 to 29% in 2023. According to the CDC, depression is up around 60% in just the past 10 years. These are just a few of the negative trends, all of which have a strong genetic component. The extent to which such trends are due to mutation accumulation remains to be shown.

Finally, consider the quintessentially human quality: intelligence. Rather like autism, intelligence is hard to define; unlike autism, we have objective data in the form of various IQ tests. Furthermore, intelligence is highly heritable, and hence largely driven by genetics. Heritability is relatively low in young children, due to temporary effects of their environment, but becomes dominant by age 10 and eventually reaches 75–80% in adults.[11] In other words, genetics accounts for up to 80% of an adult’s intelligence. Therefore, if genetics are negatively affected by dysgenic trends and accumulated mutations, it ought to eventually result in lower IQ scores across given population groups.

In fact, there is some evidence that this is happening already. Well-known in intelligence studies is the so-called Flynn Effect: a general rise in IQ scores since about 1930, at a rate of roughly 3 points per decade. This is largely attributable to environmental factors: improved education, nutrition, and other health-related benefits in the twentieth century. And given that the relaxation of selection didn’t really begin until around 1900, it is not surprising that we see no immediate detrimental effects; in fact, we should expect it to take about three or four generations to become manifest (“on the timescale of a few generations, i.e., 100 years”—Lynch). And evidence exists that this is precisely what is happening. Some studies find that the Flynn Effect began to slow in the 1970s and 1980s, flatten out, and then reverse into the 1990s; that is, IQ scores actually started to decline beginning around 1990.

Perhaps the best evidence for this anti-Flynn Effect comes from the Norwegian military, which has administered identical IQ tests to all young men of conscription age since 1957. The combined scores show a steep, 5-point-per-decade gain from 1957 to 1977, then a slower, one-point-per-decade gain until 1993, and then roughly a 2.7-point-per-decade decline through 2008 (the year that Norway began to include women in the testing cohort, thus complicating the analysis).[12] This is significant, especially considering that the reverse effect also appears in other countries. Dutton et al (2016) identify six other industrial countries with anti-Flynn trends, yielding declines ranging from 1.35 to an astonishing 8.4 IQ points per decade. We can triple these figures to get generational estimates, suggesting that successive generations are losing potentially 4 to 25 (!) IQ points. Clearly this is not sustainable, but it indicates something of the potential magnitude of the problem. As further recent confirmation, Dworak et al (2023) found a decline on the order of two IQ points per decade (six points per generation) in American adults between 2006 and 2018, in 3 of 4 cognitive domains.

For perhaps obvious reasons, only a few scientists are willing to openly address the possible effects of genetic degradation on intelligence—among those, Michael Woodley of Menie, Matt Sarraf, and Mateo Peñaherrera-Aguirre. The papers Woodley (2015; “How fragile is our intellect?”) and Woodley et al (2017; “What causes the Anti-Flynn Effect?”) are of particular interest here; the former argues for “an overall dysgenic loss” in IQ of 1.23 points per decade, or 4.31 per generation—around the low end of the range given above by Dutton. The latter paper examines four proposed causes of IQ loss and tests five specific hypotheses.

As yet further evidence of genetic degradation, Dutton observes that “a series of studies have noted declines in proxies for intelligence” (p. 164). Specifically, over the twentieth century, human reaction times have slowed, color discrimination ability has declined, and facial asymmetry has increased—all strongly genetic factors that are linked, to some degree, to intelligence.

“So what?” says the critic. “Intelligence is overrated anyway. And there are lots of different kinds of intelligences that are never measured.” Unfortunately, intelligence is related to many social characteristics that most people consider important, like economic prosperity, social and political stability, and scientific achievement, and health. And as I have noted, declines in intelligence are almost certainly paralleled by many other declines in health and well-being. It is a matter of the greatest importance.

But there may be something of a silver lining as described in Woke Eugenics: How Social Justice is a Mask for Social Darwinism. by Ed Dutton and J.O.A. Rayner-Hilles:

Wokeness is, ultimately, a group level adaptation; a vital adaptation which ensures that the group is returned to genetic mental and physical health, and, associated with this, high religiosity and ethnocentrism. The group is, therefore, able to survive the battle of group selection and, indeed, survive the next catastrophe that nature throws at us. It does this by creating an environment in which all but the extremely genetically healthy are induced to not pass on their genes.  In that sense, this blue-haired Cultural Anthropology undergraduate is a nationalist hero: she is sacrificing her own genetic interests for the good of ethnic group and, ultimately, for the survival of humanity itself.

While important, the woke phenomenon will likely not be sufficient to reverse the various declines associated with our current, rather pervasive dysgenic situation.

Some Serious Discourse

Let me, then, offer some (in Lynch’s words) “serious discourse” on this topic. For at least 300 years, Western humanity has been relaxing the evolutionary selection pressures that kept our species healthy. For 100 years, selection pressure has vanished completely, as virtually all infants survive to reproductive age. Basic genetic theory tells us that this cannot but have disastrous consequences in the future, and that, indeed, we are likely feeling them already.

Therefore, we need to reintroduce selection: artificial selection, or some system of eugenics, by which we prevent deleterious mutations from accumulating and multiplying. Such action has traditionally been called “negative eugenics” because it halts the propagation of detrimental characteristics. By contrast, there also exist strategies for “positive eugenics” which aim to promote humanity’s best qualities: beauty, intelligence, strength, creativity, and so on. Given the preexisting and inevitable near-term future decline, both strategies are necessary.

Obviously, this is a huge topic of discussion, demanding extended analyses and vigorous debate. But instead of serious examination, we get only insipid hysterics whenever the topic is broached in the public.[13] Unfortunately, positive assessments of eugenics are virtually nonexistent, and even neutral studies are rare. Ruth Cowan’s Heredity and Hope (2008) offers support for highly restricted eugenic procedures for removing the worst of our heritable genetic diseases, but this is far short of a positive endorsement of the general principle. Furthermore, Cowan is Jewish, and given that Jews have more than their share of heritable genetic diseases, it is unsurprising that she defends such policies.

As a rough outline, though, what might a contemporary eugenic program look like? We must work from first principles here, and I find four to be of central importance. First: No one has a ‘right’ to bear children. In a dysgenic world, childbearing is a privilege, not a right. A eugenic society would grant this privilege, just as present society determines laws and morals, confers citizenship, and exerts power on behalf of the collective good. This is not to say that the state will directly control childbirth; rather, births that are in accord with established eugenic policy will earn the support and blessings of society, and any that are not in accord will exist outside the sphere of the formal social system—something like undocumented immigrants are today. They would have none of the social benefits.

A second core principle relates to the notion of human equality: In no meaningful sense are all humans equal. People differ in every conceivable way: abilities, skills, interests, capabilities, intelligences, creativities, appearance, etc. People are ‘equal’ only in the most trivial senses: all are alive, all are individuals, all have wants and needs, and so on. We have to face it: There are better people, and there are lesser people—period. We all know this instinctively but are loathe to say it out loud, thanks to an entrenched cult of equality in the West (owing ultimately to Judeo-Christianity).[14] Any eugenic society will have to abandon this long-promoted but highly damaging concept, replacing it with ideas of merit, value, and individual worth.[15]

Third: Eugenics works best in ethnically homogenous societies. Multicultural or multiracial societies have highly conflicting ideas about the higher human qualities, about what should be valued the most and what the least. This situation causes myriad problems in ordinary societies today, and the conflicts would be exacerbated by any attempt to minimize, or to promote, certain genetic features. Preliminary steps should be taken, therefore, to minimize ethnic diversity prior to instituting any eugenic program.

Fourth: The best individuals have the highest obligation to the community—and vice versa. Today in the West, the best and brightest often live for themselves, for money or material pleasures, and generally pursue hedonistic lifestyles, often without bearing children. A materialist mindset is actively promoted in media, entertainment, and academia, in large part because of the dominance of Judaic values and worldview.[16] This needs to change. The best need to elevate their obligation to society, and society in turn needs to respect, honor, and reward the best who dedicate themselves to family and community. A female celebrity in a eugenic society would be an outstanding young woman with four or five children by an equally-outstanding young man, not a social media darling who prostitutes herself for cash, or a career-driven corporate executive. A male hero would be a devoted father and community leader, not a professional athlete, rap singer, or some actor in appalling Hollywood cinema. The best men and women would be people of quality, of honor, and of virtue—people who recognize their fundamental obligation to society and the community.

Putting It into Practice

Identifying the concepts and theory is relatively easy; putting eugenics into practice is much harder, especially given our present humanitarian, egalitarian, and (broadly) liberal mindset. Nature imposed a harsh but beneficial system of eugenics on humanity for its entire existence, but now, thanks to industrial technology, we have acquired the means to circumvent Nature’s plan, and we are actively doing so. Now, it is a matter of will and choice to realign with Nature—and the choices are difficult. Below I offer a few initial thoughts on how to structure such a process.

One option would be to establish unique policies for each of three social groups: (1) newborns, infants, and children up to age 15, (2) people of reproductive age (16 to 40 for women, and to 50 for men), and (3) the elders (over 40 / over 50).

The elders, being generally beyond the age of reproduction, are the easiest to address; little needs to be done for them. The largest risk, from a eugenic standpoint, is older men who might wish to be fathers despite the accumulated genetic mutations in their sperm. Fatherhood over 50 should be discouraged, and over 60, strongly discouraged.

For those of reproductive age, there needs to be an essential understanding: not all are allowed to procreate. There must be a selection process of some sort, to evaluate and identify the healthiest and the fittest, and then to encourage them to start families. Thus, everyone of this age would need to be assessed for fitness, evaluating both positive and negative characteristics, and then rated or ranked in some way. It would be, in a sense, a modern caste system—one in which the best are encouraged to mate with the best. The least among this group would be discouraged, not from marrying, but only from having children; for them, sterilization might be an alternative.

Assessments of this reproductive group would likely take on several forms: genetic testing, medical inspection, ability testing (e.g., IQ), and personal review by a panel of skilled, racially aware elders. All data would be compiled by the panel and integrated into some metric that would determine eligibility for procreation. In the end, the best half, the top 50%, would be endorsed for childbearing, and the top 25% or 10% would be strongly incentivized to do so. The lower half would be disincentivized or, in the worst cases, prohibited from having children. Again, any children arising from this group would exist outside the official social benefit system and would not be recognized as legitimate citizens of the community. Finally, all rankings would need to be public knowledge, given the intense public interest in seeing such a system succeed.

For infants and children to age 15, actions would be very limited. Their very immaturity would preclude much in the way of evaluation. Genetic testing is one obvious exception, and this could be performed on all children with the goal of identifying genetic predispositions for certain diseases or disabilities. Otherwise, the main priority with this group would be to give all the best possible environmental conditions for growth, learning, and healthy development. Upon reaching the age of 16, all would then undergo the standard evaluation process.

Note that there is no need for brutal or harsh methods, such as infanticide. It is sufficient to give all of the young the best possible environment, and then to properly assess them at reproductive age. A strongly eugenic society might restrict care given to the most disabled, but this is technically unnecessary; all that is required is that the least fit not be allowed to reproduce—this is the one non-negotiable condition. If this is done carefully, then over time, the numbers of disabled and needy should naturally decline, average fitness will increase, and society will be on the road to a prosperous future.

Such, at least, is my outline of a eugenic solution. I believe it to be quite benign and effective, achieving the end goal of a healthy, flourishing populace with a minimum of intervention. If it sounds cruel or harsh or unrealistic, it is only because we have yet to grasp the magnitude of the crisis we are facing. Those who doubt me need only wait a few more years; I suspect that, sadly, the situation will become all too obvious in the not-too-distant future.

David Skrbina, PhD, is a retired professor of philosophy. For more on his work and writings, see www.davidskrbina.com


[1] Book V, 456e. In the text, Plato discusses eugenics specifically for the “guardians”—those “best of the best” who will govern the ideal polis and defend it in battle. He does not say whether eugenics should apply to the bulk of the populace, but the principles are generic; there seems to be no reason why they cannot apply to all.

[2] Lives, “Lycurgus,” 16 (circa 100 AD).

[3] Roughly the age of 15. See “Infant and child death in the human environment of evolutionary adaptation,” A. Volk and J. Atkinson (2013), Evolution and Human Behavior 34: 182-192. In the literature, we differentiate between “infant mortality” (deaths before age 1) and “child mortality” (deaths before age 15); here, it is child mortality that is the relevant metric.

[4] The global average today is about 4.3%.

[5] Gaia theorist James Lovelock stated that humanity would be lucky to number 1 billion in the year 2100—nearly a 90% decline from current numbers. And the late Australian biologist Frank Fenner predicted that we had already passed the point of no return, and humanity would be extinct by the end of the century: global population zero.

[6] In the industrial nations today, about 75% of all men and about 80% of all women have at least one child in their lives. See A. Liu, et al (2024), “Evidence from Finland and Sweden on the relationship between early-life diseases and lifetime childlessness in men and women,” Nature Human Behaviour 8: 276–287.

[7] “Mutation and Human Exceptionalism: Our Future Genetic Load” (Genetics 202: 869-875).

[8] In less academic terms, one is reminded of the 2006 comedy satire film Idiocracy, which lampoons a future Earth ruled by imbeciles, thanks not to genetic mutation but to the less-intelligent outbreeding the more-intelligent. The mechanism is different but the outcome is comparable.

[9] See Chebib et al (2024) for a good reference list.

[10] By Matthew Sarraf, Michael Woodley of Menie, and Colin Feltham (Palgrave Macmillan).

[11] See Bouchard (2013): “The Wilson Effect: The Increase in Heritability of IQ With Age.”

[12] See Nordmo et al (2025): “Reevaluating the Flynn Effect and the Reversal” (Figure 3).

[13] Witness the recent uproar over actress Sydney Sweeney’s “good jeans/genes” ads, which were predictably blasted by the liberal media as “eugenic.”

[14] “There is neither Jew nor Gentile, neither slave nor free, nor is there male and female, for you are all one in Christ Jesus”—Paul, Gal 3:28.

[15] “That all men are equal is a proposition to which, at ordinary times, no sane human being has ever given his assent”—Aldous Huxley, Proper Studies, p. 1.

[16] Judaism and the Old Testament hold fundamentally materialist perspectives, in which success and ‘salvation’ occur in the worldly realm. For Jews, money and power are the guiding principles and highest values. All this is clearly spelled out in the Old Testament and in the Talmud. Via Jewish influence, these values are projected throughout contemporary Western society, with significant negative consequences.

Will Post-Modernity Be Post-Darwinian? A Review of “The Post-Darwinian Zoo”

The Post-Darwinian Zoo
Tibur Zorodin
Createspace, December, 2023

Perhaps all of Western socio-political history can divided into three eras: Pre-Darwinian, Darwinian, and post-Darwinian. The first period consisted of the millennia before the publication of Charles Darwin’s On the Origins of Species (1859) when men intuitively understood the importance of blood and breed, monarchy and aristocracy being the dominant ideologies. Then in the late nineteenth and early twentieth century, Darwinian evolution, combined with Mendelian genetics, began to inform public policy. President Theodore Roosevelt’s espousal of eugenics was uncontroversial, in fact eugenics was once supported across the political spectrum. Since the end of World War II public debate on, much less implementation of, “social Darwinist policies” is prohibited. The irony is that we now understand far more about human evolution and genetics than during the Progressive Era. The author is concerned that Red China might be the state where such findings find application.

We know little about the author. Tibur Zorodin is presumably a nom de plume. He is described online as a sociobiologist who “has been writing chiefly on political matters for more than a decade.”  In its broad scope and literary style The Post-Darwinian Zoo might remind the reader of The Dispossessed Majority,[1] though DM is a more tightly structured work. Zorodin’s over 900 footnotes make reference to academic journals, mainstream media, and popular culture from North America, Europe, and Australasia.

The book begins by describing how current demographic trends have become dysgenic and why it matters. Intelligence, criminality, conscientiousness, and other traits are highly heritable. The system is still able to function because “[t]he West’s upper cognitive echelon of entrepreneurs and scientists remain in place for now,” even as social pathology increases. The remedy for dysgenics is eugenics. Eugenics is not pseudoscience but applied science widely practiced in breeding plants and animals. The author makes a distinction between social Darwinism that “is more concerned with group advancement, identity, and distinctiveness,” and eugenics that “tends toward universalism and IQ absolutism.”

Eugenics need not be coercive or mandatory to be effective if a society has healthy values. Pre-natal screenings can detect congenital defects, yet in some US states it is illegal to abort a Down syndrome pregnancy. Zorodin makes the obvious point that choosing to abort a healthy pregnancy is far different than terminating an abnormal one. Furthermore, there are over 50,000 rape pregnancies annually in the US. Only half of these pregnancies are aborted. “Evolutionarily rewarding the act of rape is damaging for society both in the short term and the long term.” Yet there are states where abortion in the case of rape is not allowed. The dissident Right is, in large measure, defined by its opposition to conventional conservatism. Eugenic abortion is one of the wedge issues that divides the conservative and dissident Right. Zorodin will have some more choice words for conservatives later in the book.

The author next turns his attention to the issue of miscegenation. He provides some disturbing statistics: “92% of biracial children with a Black father are born out of wedlock and 82% end up on government assistance.” In addition, it has been reported that mixed-race children are more likely to experience anxiety and depression, abuse drugs and be truant compared to monoracial children. The “instability in biracial households and conflict in identity formation” might explain these outcomes.

Zorodin then moves from traditional eugenic measures to genetic engineering, and at times the discussion takes on a sci-fi feeling. Yet there is logic to it. Setting aside the cautionary tale of Dr. Frankenstein’s monster, the author makes the case that we can produce a freer, healthier more egalitarian society. One of the more interesting topics in this section are the five or so pages devoted to human beauty. This segment runs parallel to the “Esthetic Prop” theory in the aforementioned Dispossessed Majority. The author believes there is “an innate preference” for light coloration, height, and symmetry. Despite claims by Left activists that short, dark, and dumpy is just as attractive as tall, fair, and svelte “[t]he notion of esthetic egalitarianism is fundamentally incompatible with human psychology.”

The advantages of ethnic homogeneity, such as those expressed by John Jay in Federalist Papers 2, have been known for centuries. Zorodin reports on some lesser-known benefits of such societies. For example, “a multiracial society could be responsible for increasing the rate of gender dysphoria and sexual divergence.” Also, military personnel who served in homogeneous units are “more functional and cohesive,” and these veterans are less likely to suffer PTSD than those from heterogeneous units.

Decades ago, the famous research psychologist Raymond Cattell proposed a social experiment where small nations—mini ethno-states—would compete socially and economically by nonviolent means.[2]  Zorodin suggests something similar: “Various statelets and autonomous regions around the world harbor the potential for eugenic-minded communities to be formalized and legitimized; [thereby] offering . . .  life under a system of consensual social Darwinism.”

The author’s criticism of the contemporary Right extends to economics. He takes exception to the produce-and-consume economic model that features  ”gross expansion” over improved productivity via efficiency. The West’s “growth fetishism has discarded all caution of long-term cultural compatibility in pursuit of short-term economic stimulus” brought about through immigrant labor and consumption. The GDP will increase as the quality of life decreases.

Colorblind—perhaps completely blind—conservatives come under more criticism “King’s Manifesto from 1963 [‘I Have a Dream’] would in contemporary politics equate to a platform in the Republican Party.” Establishment conservatives’ maxim: “If you can’t beat them, join them in their tradition of chasing second place on the right side of history.”

Zorodin’s literary style makes the book both a pleasure and a challenge to read. Regarding Angela Merkel’s decision to open Germany’s border to mass migration: “It is hardly a top-down revolution, since the supporting convoy of Zeitgeist peers has no shortage of ethnomasochistic gluttons breaking the backs of their high-horses.” Find out which two countries are most “oikophobic.”

In fact, Zorodin devotes a section to language. He defends, as I do, the use of the term ‘Cultural Marxism’ because it is “consistent with the radical pedigree and an analogous group-conflict theoretical model” of orthodox Marxism. “The plasticity of language in the information age has never before been so amenable to socially-engineered neologisms with political agendas.” So illegal aliens become undocumented migrants, and the sexually confused are gender nonconforming. In addition, these “euphemisms appear to have an expiry date.” There is a “euphemism treadmill,” so the feeble-minded become the mentally retarded become the developmentally impaired.

The author uses the example of the near-seamless large-scale assimilation of Germans into American society to segue to the Jewish Question. That question is: What has been and should be the role of Jews in Western civilization? The last 35 pages or so of the book is a survey course on Jews. First, in contrast to German-Americans, Jewish-Americans have not, by in large, identified with traditional American culture. Their wealth and organizational acumen have led to an “undue influence on the institutions of public life, at the expense of heritage America.” The well-known Jewish financial crimes, the kosher certification racket, and the Sackler family pill mill Purdue Pharma are covered. All this is mediated by the “guilt prescription” of the Holocaust. The book has a quote from former Israeli foreign minister Abba Ebon: “There’s no business like Shoah business.”

Probably the most interesting aspect of this topic is Judeo-Christian Zionism. Zorodin has hammered the establishment Right for its social and economic policies, now it is time to consider its perverse foreign policy. Possibly the most perverted feature of cuckservativism is its slavish devotion to Israel. The author describes it as “surrogate nationalism.” In a warped way it serves as a “politically correct outlet” for the ethnonationalism establishment conservatives deny their own people. Border security for the US is a good political talking point, but border security for Israel is a cause for urgent action. Speaker of the US House of Representatives Mike Johnson intones: “It’s a Biblical admonition to stand with Israel.” Whether the current conflict in the Levant will change present political calculations remains to be seen.

The book ends rather abruptly. There is no summary or concluding chapter to bring together all the many issues and ideas presented. The reader does not get to see what compound the combined elements might produce. So here is my takeaway from the Post Darwinian Zoo:

The title implies we are now living in zoo world—society as a menagerie—filled with strange and diverse creatures. It is widely believed that the modern era is coming to an end. The question becomes: Is the present cultural disintegration a beginning or the end? Is what we see today just a foretaste of a chaotic post-modern age?  Or, will post-modernity usher in a Western instauration, a new renaissance? At one point, Zorodin appears pessimistic. For we are “in the twilight of late modernity and at the terminal stage of human cultural evolution.” But he holds out hope if we are able to think outside the box. Conservatism is safe and respectable, but it is an ineffective and at times counterproductive strategy for opposing the forces that seek to destroy Western culture and peoples.

The book deals with many interesting topics not mentioned in this short review. There is some high protein food for thought here, and even the best informed and knowledgeable reader should find some new insights on human biology, culture, and the social sciences. I give this book a very solid recommendation. That said, a stronger thematic organization would make the information more assimilable.


[1] Wilmot Robertson, The Dispossessed Majority (1972).

[2] Raymond Cattell, A New Morality from Science: Beyondism (1973); Raymond Cattell Beyondism: A Religion from Science (1987).

William Gayley Simpson on Christianity and the West

William Gayley Simpson in the early 1940s

The following is adapted from a book I wrote based on interviews with the late white activist William Pierce, The Fame of a Dead Man’s Deeds.

“Someone else you might want to include in this [book] project,” Pierce called out to me as I was leaving his office at the end of one of our evening talks, “is William Gayley Simpson.  Do you know about him?”

Very little.  All I knew about Simpson was that he had written a book called Which Way Western Man? (free pdf) and that Pierce had published it under his own imprint, National Vanguard Books.  I hadn’t read the book.

“Simpson was born in 1892, the same year as my father,” Pierce continued, “so he was a generation ahead of me.  In the ’30s he was interacting with the public in a big way, speaking at a lot of universities, mostly about peace issues, how we must never get into another world war and that sort of thing, and at one time he taught Latin, mathematics, and history at a boarding school around where he lived in New York state.  Somehow, he had gotten hold of something I had written—this must have been around 1975—and he wrote me about it.  At that time, he was over 80-years-old [he died in 1991 at 99].

“We started corresponding.  I found Simpson to be a deep, sensitive, and serious man.  He invited me to visit him up at his farm.   He had built a farmhouse with his own hands, a really nice house, and he had a shop and outbuildings.  He did some planting, but mostly he just lived there and thought and wrote and maintained contact [letters in those days] with people from all over the world.  I stayed with him a few days and visited him a couple more times after that.

“Simpson told me about a book he was finishing up, which turned out to be Which Way Western Man?  I read it and was very impressed and published it.  We sold that printing, and then we did two more printings, about seven thousand copies, and sold out on those.   Let me get you a copy of Which Way Western Man?

Pierce stood up from his desk, turned to his left, took a couple of steps, and turned left again through an open door into his library.  I followed.   It was dark in there—I could barely make out the titles of the books.  It was a good-sized room, about fifteen-by-twenty feet.  It reminded me of the stacks in a university library, the same kind of metal shelving.   Rows of shelves tightly packed from floor to ceiling with books spanned the room’s interior.  Pierce had labels taped onto the shelves categorizing his collection, so he knew right where to find the Simpson book.  I stood behind him and took in this tall grey-haired man standing in this gloomy library as he turned a few pages of the Simpson book, his eyes just a few inches from the print as he had very poor sight.  

Pierce handed me the bulky, dark blue paperback.  My hand gave way a bit from the weight of what I later learned was a 758-page volume.

I thanked Pierce for the book and told him I would spend the rest of that evening and the next day looking it over, and that if I could get my thoughts organized I’d talk to him the next evening about what Simpson had written.   Read more

“The Book and the Rifle”: Cultural and Racial Policy in Fascist Italy, Part 3

difesa_della_razza

Eugenics and Racial Policy

Tarquini devotes substantial attention to race and eugenics in Italian culture under Fascism. She notes that the Fascist government gave Italian eugenic scientists support and attention which they had never enjoyed under previous regimes:

From 1922 to 1945 Italian scientists contributed to racial culture and policy. These included anthropologists, statisticians, demographers, and doctors who were already well-known in the scientific world in the early years of the century, when demography and eugenics — the science which studies the methods to perfect the human species by favoring the proliferation of individuals deemed best (positive eugenics) or through the suppression of individuals considered harmful (negative eugenics) — brought their attention to the demographic decline present in many Western countries. … With the advent of fascism these scientists played a role which they did not have in previous regimes. In exchange they offered the totalitarian and racist policy their own generous support. (pp. 201–202)

Demographic issues were given particular attention in the aftermath of the massive bloodletting of World War I and a significant fall in the birth rates of Western countries. Read more

The Assault on Gender and the Family: Jewish Sexology and the Legacy of the Frankfurt School, Part One

“Sexual morality — as society, in its extreme form, the American, defines it — seems to me very contemptible. I advocate an incomparably freer sexual life.”                                                                                        Sigmund Freud, 1908.

“There will be other forms in addition to our classic marriage…We will experience a broader spectrum of socially accepted forms of sexual life.”                                                                                                           Volkmar Sigusch, 2015.

sigusch

Volkmar Sigusch

Volkmar Sigusch (1940- ) may not be a familiar name to TOO readers, but for those concerned about the modern assault on traditional attitudes to gender and sexuality it should be. You might have encountered the term ‘cisgender,’ a Sigusch creation that is rapidly gaining traction in common speech. For those unfamiliar with it, it has come to replace “normal” and even the more deviant-friendly term ‘heterosexual.’ Specifically, the term refers to those “who feel there is a match between their assigned sex and the gender they feel themselves to be. You are cisgender if your birth certificate says you’re male and you identify yourself as a man.” The goal behind inventing such a bizarre and convoluted label for that which is natural and healthy is, of course, to further dilute the identity of the present and coming generations, and convince us all that there is no “normal,” only different positions within an ever more colorful spectrum.

By undermining the meaning of what it is to be male and female, one undermines the healthy concept of the family. And when the healthy concept of the family possessed by a given group is undermined, that group is pushed ever closer to genocide via (using the United Nations lexicon) “deliberate infliction of conditions of life calculated to bring about its physical destruction in whole or in part,” and “imposing measures intended to prevent births.” The bumper crop of terms like ‘cisgender’, cooked up with alarming frequency by the “sexologists,” helps reduce marriage between a man and a woman and the raising of children within that union, to a mere “option” on a veritable menu of possible sexualities, gender identities, and family structures. In this brave new world there is no “normal” or “ideal” since all “models” are allegedly valid and equal. Read more

Eugenics and the Age of the Demon

‘Everything is done to encourage the mad increase in number and that constant loss in quality. Everything is done to keep the sickly, the cripple, the freaks of nature, the unfit to work and unfit to live, from dying.’
        Savitri Devi, The Lightning and the Sun

There are many glaring ways in which degeneracy is embraced in this slow unfolding of the Kali Yuga.  The ancient Hindus, closely related to us by blood, believed that prior to an age of rebirth, the last stage in the cyclical existence of the world would be a time of great strife and hardship for the righteous. The Kali Yuga (Age of the Demon) would be typified by lying governments, the mass migration of peoples to the wealthier portions of the globe, increased addiction to drugs and alcohol, and rampant sexual permissiveness. Perhaps one of the most momentous signs of the coming end was also to be the widespread abandonment and ignorance of dharma, a word with multiple meanings but which can be best conceived as referring to behaviours and attitudes conducive to the laws and order of the universe. Most simply, dharma is all that contributes to the ‘right way of living,’ to the natural order, and to life itself. Dharma holds back chaos, and acts for the cohesiveness and health of the individual, the family, and the community.

Conceived as such, it is clear that dharma is a rare commodity in today’s world. The profane has been declared natural, and all that is healthy and natural has been pathologized and degraded. Dharma, thus conceived, commands ‘right behavior,’ as well as the existence of clear delineations in gender, sexuality, and race. All of these delineations are being gleefully abandoned or assaulted by the hedonists, the gullible, and the insidious architects of decay. The cutting edge of the sexual revolution has taken its most recent form in the popular celebration and endorsement of homosexual marriage, a literal paradox and an affront to nature. The recent craze over the mental, and now physical, deformity of former athlete Bruce Jenner, merely confirms the frenzied addiction the modern West has to the dysfunctional, the freakish, and the maladaptive. Read more